Senin, 22 April 2013

Ibn Taymiyyah On the Existense of God


Grasping Ibn Taymiyyahs idea on the existence of God is somewhat difficult as he only makes brief comments on the problem in his treatises. Another problem is that his discourse is highly polemical and refutative, particularly when he rejects certain philosophical and theological arguments that he believes to be false or lacking validity, he does not always provide an alternative argument.  However, this does not preclude the possibility of discovering Ibn Taymiyyahs argument on the existence of God. This is discernable  through his various works which deal with logic, theology, legal opinions and certainly metaphysics. Therefore, understanding his attitude towards the philosophical doctrine on logic is pivotal for comprehending his thought, since logic is connected to and instrumental for his rebuttal of metaphysics.
As Ibn Taymiyyah realised,  the philosophers way of proving the existence of God is dominated by  their  theory of  being, which rests basically on the theory of essence.72  Essence in this theory has no connection with  existence, as existence is superadded to quiddity and can be either in the mind or in the external world. On the other hand, an essence in itself can be universal in the mind when it is abstracted from extra mental particulars. 
In the frame of Ibn Taymiyyahs  criticism, this point could bring us to his basic concept of Gods existence. To him, the essence is no more than a generalization or abstraction by the mind of an externally existing individuals, 73 and therefore it has no existence other than in the mind.74   In being consonant to this, Ibn Taymiyyah holds that the  universal can never exist in the extra mental world, but only in the mind.75  To him, external individuals cannot be formed into an external universal, as individuals, even if some of their aspects are similar, cannot be entirely identical.76   Accordingly, all universals  have only a mental existence, exactly like absolute existence when it is  conditioned or unconditioned by anything.77  If absolute existence is a merely mental concept, then the Necessary Existence does not exist in external reality, but only in the mind.78
It seems that Ibn Taymiyyahs rebuttal of the philosophers theory of universals, leads him to reject the use of  syllogism  (qiyÉs al-shumËl). This is because the philosophers knowledge of Necessary Existence is actually knowledge of  a particular in whom plurality could be perceived. Therefore, Necessary Existence  cannot  be proven by means of syllogisms.79  Moreover, he believes that there is nothing in the conclusion  that is not already found in the premises, even if the syllogism is valid.  For being so,  the syllogism is not the right way to introduce new knowledge of the real world.80  Similarly, when this categorical  syllogism is utilized to prove the existence of God, it does not bring  new knowledge, for this could be known  merely by statement and not necessarily by syllogistic proof.
Furthermore, Ibn Taymiyyah asserts that proving the existence of the Creator does not depend on syllogisms. This  is because what is achieved by syllogism is the same as what is obtained by way of analogy and the result will be a universal matter common to everything others than God,  and it does not lead to the knowledge which is only particular to the Lord.81  Adopting an empiricist view of knowledge, he argues that, leaving aside revelation, the process of acquiring knowledge begins with the experience of particular objects and events through sense perception. The formation of the universal in the mind begins with the observation of particulars, if those qualities found in a number of observed particulars are extracted, the formation of a general notion of such existing particulars becomes possible.82  In extracting such qualities a man relies on his capacity to draw an analogy between one particular and another.  It is by using the existing particular and the tool of analogy that the universal concept can be found. Be that as it may, God cannot be subject to analogical inference since He is certainly unlike any other being. As God is not amenable to analogy, He cannot be included in a universal proposition. Thus, neither analogy nor syllogisms are instrumental to provide proof of His existence.83
Alternatively, Ibn Taymiyyah introduces two means by which Gods existence may be known. The first is by intuition involving no inference, and the second is by exercising the faculty of reasoning.84  The first, which is called the  fiÏrah, is the way that to which Ibn Taymiyyah always reiterates to comprehend Gods existence.85  This concept has been elaborated previously in his thought on logic.86  It indicates the innate faculty of perception that produce a concept in human minds. However, in the opinion of Ibn Taymiyyah it is a source or mechanism for acquiring knowledge which involves no inferential process.  Unlike the mind (aql) whose function is to conduct inferential operations, the notion of the  fiÏrah is that  God is known through mans awareness that  God is the self-evident truth,  and this knowledge is  necessarily  valid.  It is also known from mans general consciousness of the divine attributes that God is the Almighty and the Unique, who is not comparable to anything else.87
Moreover, the knowledge of Gods existence is necessarily  (darË) ingrained in a sound, healthy fiÏrah, and requires no inference whatsoever.88  The term darË89 is frequently used by Ibn Taymiyyah when he explains the concept of the  fiÏrah.  It is a way by which people attain knowledge in the mind, while being unaware of that process.90  Once this knowledge is attained in the mind, the cause is not always clear. This is because sometimes the knowledge is attained at once, like that which is attained by sense perception, in other cases it is attained gradually, like the knowledge  of  ‘the multiply transmitted report (khabar al-mutawÉtir).91 Regarding Gods existence, once the concept of  particulars such as miracle, tree or animal enters the domain of  cognisance, the  fiÏrah necessarily (darËratan) apprehends Gods existence. Also when the fiÏrah observes a human in existence, it instinctively realizes that there is  a Creator, for a human can never create himself.92 Thus, by  the  fiÏrah one can innately know  that  every created thing must necessarily have a Creator.
Based on this concept, it is clear that there are instinctive volition (al-irÉdah al-fiÏriyyah) and  knowledge (al-marifah al-fiÏriyyah) in the mind. Some times knowledge and volition are attained by action (fi‘l) or by power resulting from action. If the mind perceives something bad, it refers to the existing knowledge and volition in the mind or turns to its purpose, which is to attain knowledge and love of God. It is because God creates man that he has the natural disposition of loving and knowing Him. This is what Ibn Taymiyyah calls  al-HanÊfiyyah  (The true Religion). 93 It seems  that Ibn Taymiyyah tries to relate the concept of fiÏrah in terms  of human inclination towards truth and fiÏrah in the sense of natural disposition  of  knowing and loving God.
However, Ibn Taymiyyah admits that acquiring knowledge of Gods existence by means of natural fiÏrah is to grasp truth  in a general sense, for the natural fiÏrah implanted in the human mind is incomplete. Therefore, it is completed by the sent-down fiÏrah (al-fiÏrah al-munazzalah), which is the revealed religion.  Religion gives more detail and complete elaboration of truth, providing a framework for  the natural fiÏrah.94  For this,  Ibn Taymiyyah gives the non-inferred and self-evident truths of  scripture at the same value as the truth of intuitive knowledge acquired through fiÏrah. True information about God is, therefore, known from God through the QurÉn and the Sunnah.95
Consequently, all mans intellectual activities, such as inference, reasoning, reflection and the like, will lead to truth if they are based on scriptural precepts, the highest form of truths based on self-evident and non-inferred premises. The result of this process will necessarily be true knowledge and guidance.96 As God creates the  fiÏrah in a sound and perfect condition, the  falsehoods found in the thought of individuals are due to their own error.97
The second method is by exercising the faculty of reasoning (naÐar). Ibn Taymiyyahs early statement that to prove the existence of God needs no inference whatsoever,98 suggests that this method is ambivalent.  But, if Ibn Taymiyyahs division of knowledge is put into context, there is no contradiction at all. Knowledge, to him, is of two kinds: necessary (al-ilm al-d}arË) and inferential (al-ilm al-naÐarÊ).99   The former is acquired through the  necessary instinctive methods (al-Ïuruq al-darËriyyah al-fiÏriyyah), which is  naturally implanted in the human minds and is indeed the origin of the latter.100  The latter is attained by inference (al-naÐar), which to Ibn Taymiyyah can be of two types: inference in search of indication (al-naÐar Ïalaban li al-dalÊl ), like inquiring about someone who claims  prophethood, and inference on the indication  (al-naÐar fÊ al-dalÊl), like the reasoning of  the QurÉnic verses  and al-Hadith.101  Subsequently,  all acquired knowledge is attained by means of inference from premises which are known without inference. This is because if  the premise is known through inference it will depend on another,102 and it will become relative. Moreover, Ibn Taymiyyah also sees the possibility of  subsuming  a particular under a universal proposition by means of sense perception (al-hiss), but not by means of syllogisms.103 Thus, he thinks that proving the existence of  God by means of the inferential method is possible, though   this  is not  better than necessary instinctive knowledge. It is because of this perception that he believes there is no contradiction between reason and revelation.
Taking the above method a step further,  Ibn Taymiyyah  deduces two methods of proving the existence of God. These are  alternatives to  syllogism which has been discussed previously in his thought about logic.104  They  are inference by signs (al-istidlÉl bi-l-ÉyÉt) and a fortiori argument (qiyÉs al-awlÉ ).  As far as proving the existence of God is concerned, the first method assumes  that all existing things  in the world are   signs (ÉyÉt) of  God, whether insects, the sun, a stone, a river, a mountain, etc.  Just as we observe light,  we will know with certainty that there is a sun.  In other words, every existing thing in the world  must have a Creator of whom all  creatures are necessarily in need. 105  Secondly by  a fortiori argument  is meant that  the existence of God is  conceived through the relationship between the qualities found in the created universe and those similar  qualities found in the Creator.  Employing the terms ‘necessary and ‘possible  Ibn Taymiyyah demonstrates that the Necessary being and the possible being have the same quality of ‘existence, but the ‘existence of God  is unlike that of possible beings; the former has permanent qualities that  differ sharply from those of all possible beings.106  
This might seems that by a fortiori argument,  Ibn Taymiyyah is permitting analogy between God and created things. However, looking at the procedure he employs,  it appears  different from analogy.  The argument is that the qualities or attributes which are affirmed of God are,  to an incomprehensible extent, greater than all that is affirmed of all other beings. Understanding the incomprehensible greatness of Gods attributes, will lead  the mind to what is particular to God and impossible of application for anything other than God.  The problem is that although  this is  not analogy in the general sense of the term, Ibn Taymiyyah employs the very term used for analogy, which is qiyÉs.  Therefore, this method is not found under general heading of ‘logic,  he must have coined it himself.
To sum up,  Ibn Taymiyyahs ideas to prove the existence of God consist generally of two aspects: first  by  exercising the internal capacity of human beings,  which is the natural  instinct  (fiÏrah), and second  by utilizing the rational  faculty  by perceiving the signs of God in external reality and  understanding natural phenomena  with a fortiori analogy.  However, it seems that Ibn Taymiyyah restricts the use of speculative reason  that may contradict the rational proof of  revelation.  While he admits the possibility of inferred knowledge ( ilm al-naÐarÊ ) resulting from  logical deduction he sees it as inferior to intuitive knowledge (al-ma‘ifah al-fiÏriyyah).


72 Vide supra, “On Contingent Being and Gods Existence, Chapter III, 2.
73 al-Radd, ed. Abd al-Øamad, pp.118, 368. MajmË‘at al-FatÉwÉ, vol. IX, pp. 118, 238.
74 al-Radd,  ed. Abd al-Øamad, p. 9.
75 Naq al-ManÏiq,  pp.164, 194-196, MuwÉfaqat, vol. I, pp. 128-129; al-Radd, ed.Abd al-Øamad, pp. 22-30, 62-80.
76 MuwÉfaqat, vol.I, pp. 128-129.
77 Ibid, p.174.
78 Ibid, pp. 128-129; “al-FurqÉn, in  MajmË‘at al-RasÉil al-KubrÉ,  p.118.
79 MajmË‘at al-FatÉwÉ, vol. IX, pp. 130-131.
80  al-Radd,  ed.Abd al-Øamad, pp.  251-252, 355, 293;  MajmË‘at  al-FatÉwÉ, vol.  IX, pp. 218, 235. The ground of this accusation is that the universal premises in syllogism is regarded by Ibn Taymiyyah as not truly universal. They are formed through an enumeration of particulars which is only the work of the mind and not of the actual enumeration of all instance found in the world. It is therefore, not tenable and no more certain than the knowledge derived from the actual particulars that were subject to our sense perception. See NaqÌ  al-ManÏiq, pp. 186-8, 202-3, 206-7;  MajmË‘at al-FatÉwÉ, IX, pp. 113, 235.
81al-Radd,  ed. R.‘Ajam, vol. II, pp. 96, 100; MajmË‘at al-FatÉwÉ, vol. IX,  p. 235.
82 NaqÌ  al-ManÏiq, pp. 188, 196, 206;  MuwÉfaqat,  vol.II, p. 222, al-Radd,  ed. Abd al-Øamad,  p. 368; MajmË‘at al-FatÉwÉ, vol. IX, p. 238.
83 MuwÉfaqat, vol.I, p,14, MajmË‘at al-FatÉwÉ, vol. IX,  p. 141.
84 al-Radd,  ed. Abd al-Øamad,  pp. 254-255;  MajmË‘at al-FatÉwÉ, vol. IX, p. 213.
85 MuwÉfaqat,  vol.II, pp. 10, 254, 263;  NaqÌ  al-ManÏiq,  p. 30.
86 Vide  supra, “On the concept of FiÏrah, Chapter, IV, 2.a.
87 NaqÌ  al-ManÏiq,  pp. 38-39.
89 Ibn Taymiyyah  expounds three meanings of the term ÌarËrÊ   in relation to FiÏrah: first, it is a  common  external  knowledge  required by man. Second, it is knowledge that is perceived by the  mind without any learning process. Third, it is knowledge that  has no doubt in it and  the fourth is what   entails  in the human mind that cannot be separated. See  Dar Ta‘ÉruÌ,  vol. VII, p. 422.
90 It is like intention (niyyah) and volition (irÉdah), which are in the heart. Volition is already exists in human minds,  but they are dubious or could not express its existence in their mind, so does the necessary knowledge ( al-ilm al-ÌarËrÊ ).  See  Ibid,   p. 424.
91 Ibid,  p. 424.
93 Dar Ta‘ÉruÌ, vol. VII, p. 426. 
95 Ibid, pp.38-39, See The QurÉn, 7:53; 10:3; 25:59; 13:2; 32:4; 57:4.
96 NaqÌ  al-ManÏiq,   p. 35.
97 MuwÉfaqat, vol. II, p. 253.
98 al-Radd, ed. Abd al-Øamad,  p. 356.
99 Dar Ta‘ÉruÌ, vol.  V,  p. 312.
100 Ibid; See also al-Jalayand, M.S, TaqrÊb al-TurÉth Dar Ta‘ÉruÌ al-‘Aql wa al-Naql, Li Shaykh Al-IslÉm Ibn Taymiyyah, Markaz al-AhrÉm, Cairo 1988, p. 136.
101 This idea is Ibn Taymiyyahs  response to  a dispute among  Muslim  thinkers whether the naÐar  (reasoning) for knowing God is compulsory for every  believer or not.  Ibn Taymiyyah was in favour of making it compulsory, but he has different  ideas  on the type of compulsory reasoning.  Unlike the philosophers who assume naÐar   to be  speculation,  Ibn Taymiyyah sees   compulsory  reasoning  as ‘reasoning  on  the indication  (al-dalÊl)  to know what is indicated (al-madlËl ) it is  not ‘reasoning   in search of the indication, as the latter will not provide knowledge. As far as naÐar  for knowing God is concerned, Ibn Taymiyyah  suggests that in perceiving  the indication  one  should not be doubtful  on what is indicated (al-madlËl), because that doubt  may  be  from the ignorance of the  heart  about  the indication  and  what  is  indicated.  See Dar Ta‘ÉruÌ, VII, pp. 405-420.
102 al-Jalayand, M.S., TaqrÊb al-TurÉth, p. 207.
103 MajmË‘at al-FatÉwÉ, vol. IX, p. 235. Dar Ta‘ÉruÌ, vol. VII, p. 241; MuwÉfaqat, vol. II, pp.  254-255.
104 Vide supra, “On QiyÉs”, Chapter, IV, 2.c.
105MajmË‘at al-FatÉwÉ, vol. IX, p. 212.
106 An analogue of such differentiation is the whiteness found in snow and ivory; both have a white colour, but the strength of whiteness of snow is different from the whiteness of the ivory.  This implies that all qualities of created beings, like love, mercy, generosity and others are predicated in God in a more powerful and accentuated form.   See MajmË‘at al-FatÉwÉ, vol. IX,  p.145;  see also “TawhÊd al-UlËhiyyah,  in MajmË‘at al-FatÉwÉ, vol. I, p.48.
ic";mso� BPi l � � ��Z N-GB'>[12]  al-Radd, ed.Abd al-Øamad, p. 282.
[13] al-Radd, ed. R.‘Ajam, vol. I, p. 158;  MajmË‘at al-FatÉwÉ, vol. IX, p. 141.
[14] al-NashshÉr, ManÉhij  al-Bahth,  p. 216.
[15] MajmË‘at  al-FatÉwÉ,  vol. IX, p. 142.
[16] The  QurÉn,  17: 12.
[17] al-Radd,  ed.Abd al-Øamad, pp. 348-350.
[18]  MajmË‘at al-FatÉwÉ,   vol. IX, p. 145.
[19] al-Radd,  ed.R.‘Ajam, vol. I. p. 162; MajmË‘at  al-FatÉwÉ,  vol. IX, p. 145.
[20] MajmË‘at  al-FatÉwÉ,  vol. IX, p. 145.

Tidak ada komentar:

Posting Komentar

Jalaluddin Rumi, Penyair Sufi Terbesar dari Konya-Persia

          Dua orang bertengkar sengit di suatu jalan di Konya. Mereka saling memaki, “O, laknat, jika kau mengucapkan sepatah makian terh...