Ibn Taymiyyah’s major criticism of logic is
focused on the logic of Aristotle and of those Muslim philosophers and
theologians who followed him. This can be seen in his Radd,
where Ibn Taymiyyah attacks not
only the ideas of Aristotle but also
those of Fakhr al-DÊn al-RÉzÊ (d.606
A.H./1209), ÓmidÊ (d.632 A.H./1234), UrmawÊ (d.682 A.H/1283), Ibn SÊnÉ (d.428 A.H./1037) and other speculative theologians. Historically, the logic of Aristotle penetrated the pale of Muslim theology and
produced philosophical theologians who employed
logic in the Islamic religious sciences. For this background Rescher infers that logic in Islam was wholly based on Greek
tradition as it was transmitted through Hellenistic Aristotelianism.[1] However, this is not the case, Ibn
Taymiyyah’s criticism of Aristotelian
logic is not the first in the history of
Islamic thought. There had been
refutations by Muslim scholars of Aristotelian philosophy and logic since its
early period of transmission,[2] and there had been disputes among
Muslim scholars regarding the application of Aristotelian logic in religious discourse.[3] This historical facts could be
understood that Muslim had their own logical tool before they encounter
Aristotelian logic and hence became resistant of it.
From the achievement of his predecessors, Ibn
Taymiyyah must have learned much and gained some pivotal inputs that enriched
his critical approach towards logic. His criticism, therefore, sometimes refers
directly to the logic of Aristotle and sometimes to the Muslim logicians, but
essentially his criticism is
centred on Aristotle’s concept of definition (al-hadd)
and syllogism (al-qiyÉs).[4] In this chapter we shall
elaborate first his attitude towards logic and then his criticism of logical
definition and syllogism.
His attitude towards logic
Since Ibn Taymiyyah believes that logic ( al-ManÏiq)
is basically
Greek and has very little to do with the original Islamic doctrines, he has a
negative attitude towards it.[5] He also assumes
that when the Muslim logicians speak of definition they know that it was introduced by Aristotle, whom they held in great respect.
This belief can be traced from the fact that the subject matter of logic (al-ManÏiq) was a translation and reorganisation of Aristotelian logic,
as can be seen from the fact that the
organisation of the subject matter of al-ManÏiq is identical to
Aristotle’s organon.[6] However, the Muslims made some important contributions to the Aristotelian
system. Ibn Taymiyyah believes that dealing with Aristotelian logic is
dangerous and useless; he says:
It (al-ManÏiq)
is partly true and partly false. Most of
the truth it contains is not needed. The extent to which it is needed can be
afforded by sound fiÏrah (instinct). The danger is more than the benefit,
especially for one who is not conversant with
the knowledge of the prophets.
[7]
Furthermore, Ibn Taymiyyah points out that the art of logic invented by the First
Teacher, Aristotle, has two measuring instruments to achieve philosophical
ends: speculation and practice. Speculative knowledge contains truth that has benefit for mankind. The most reliable speculative knowledge is Mathematical
science. But, on metaphysics, or al- ‘lm al-IlÉhÊ, Ibn Taymiyyah is doubtful that philosophers
can attain salvation and happiness, since this science is unable to reach certitude (yaqÊn), being mere
assumption and mostly contrary to the messages
of the prophets. On the practical sciences that include the improvement of
morality, family and social life, Ibn Taymiyyah admits that they had notable
achievements and true ideas. However, in
his view, in the area of morality the
Greek philosophers are inferior to the prophets, for the latter have more
authority than the Greek philosophers who had no revealed book and did not believe in prophets.[8] This statement arises from his belief, as a theologian, that knowledge about morality comes only from God
through the prophets, since the rank of the prophets is higher than that of any
other human being.
Ibn Taymiyyah concluded that the ideas of Aristotle and Plato were adopted by
the Muslim philosophers, especially when such ideas affirmed the
eternity of the universe and characterised God in ways that exist only in the
mind. Elaborating this problem, he refers to the way logicians deal with
heological philosophy. He argues that it should employ neither simple analogical
syllogisms (qiyÉs al-tamthÊl) where
the branches (furË’) and the roots (uÎËl)
are similar, nor simple syllogism (qiyÉs al-shumËl) where the individuals are similar. This is
because God is not similar to anything and because it is unlawful to make Him
identical with others. It is also unlawful to include Him under a universal
premise on one level with an individual.[9] Ibn Taymiyyah refutes this method, since he believes that the mutafalsifah and mutakallimËn
could not attain
certitude, or might even end in
self-contradiction as they employ it.
The attitude of Ibn Taymiyyah was most probably
inspired by the situation at the time of al-GhazzÉli (450-505 A.H./1058-1111),
a century before, when Aristotelian
logic penetrated and was employed in
religious knowledge. al-Ghazzali
was accused of blending Aristotelian logic with al-Fiqh and uÎËl
al-Fiqh.[10] Ibn Taymiyyah, referring to
al-Ghazzali’s book al-QisÏÉs al-MustaqÊm, refutes
al-Ghazzali’s claim that the book
derives from the teachings of the Prophet,
stating that in fact it comes from Aristotle through Ibn SÊna.[11] Further, al-Ghazzali wrote an
introduction to Aristotelian logic in
his work al-MustaÎfÉ,[12] in which he made a most
controversial statement on logic, namely that “whosoever does not know logic,
his knowledge is not reliable at all.[13] Perhaps the prevailing legal opinion that studying
logic is a duty of the Muslim (farÌ kifÉyah), is ascribed to al-Ghazzali’s statements.[14] Discussing this situation in his
MajmË‘at al-FatÉwÉ,[15] Ibn Taymiyyah stated his legal opinion by replying to the question whether it is right
or wrong that studying logic is a duty (farÌ kifÉyah). To justify his attitude
to logic he mentions the arguments of Shafi’ite and Hanafite imams and other Muslim scholars.
In short, being a follower of the Salaf, Ibn Taymiyyah regards the study of logic
as unnecessary. He argues that Muslim
scholars did not employ Aristotelian logic before it became a part
of Arabic thought, even though he does
not deny that at a later period some scholars of Fiqh and UsËl al-Fiqh started
using logic. However, he emphasises that
the first three generations in Islam, the period of the Salaf did not use logic.
Moving aside from Ibn Taymiyyah’s attitude towards logic, we turn to his criticism
of logic. However, before we go into the detail of Ibn Taymiyyah’s criticism we shall first examine his
understanding of Aristotle’s logic. In his KitÉb al-Radd ‘ alÉ al-ManÏiqiyyÊn,[16] Ibn Taymiyyah encapsulates the
basic principle of the philosophers in their theory of science. He states that
according to Aristotelian logic, all scientific knowledge is based on concepts
(al-taÎawwur) and judgements (al-taÎdÊq). This kind of knowledge can be either
self-evident ( badÊhÊ ) or speculative ( naz}arÊ ). The two
methods of obtaining true knowledge are definition (al-hadd) and
syllogisms (al-qiyÉs). Definition is used for obtaining concepts. This mode of analysing
reality identifies the qualities of the
defined objects which are essential ( haqÊqiyyÉt or dhÉtiyyÉt ) or
accidental (‘ardiyyÉt ). Therefore, it must
contain genus (al-jins) and differentia ( al-faÎl).[17] However, since reality is so
complex that definition alone cannot explain it, logicians use rational means, namely syllogism.
It is used for obtaining judgement. Unlike definition, which is used for
attaining perceptual knowledge,
syllogism is used for obtaining rational knowledge proceeding from what
is given to what is not given. In other words, if some statements are accepted,
other statements necessarily follow from them.[18] Hence definition and syllogism
are two fundamental bases on which the whole structure of Aristotelian logic
stands. Therefore, the refutation by Ibn
Taymiyyah of Aristotelian logic refers to these two fundamental bases:
definition and syllogism. To fully appreciate the important criticisms of Ibn
Taymiyyah on logic, his two works Naqd al-ManÏiq and al-Radd ‘alÉ al-ManÏ}iqiyyÊn, will be
referred to in what follows.
[1] Rescher, Nicholas, Studies In The History of Arabic Logic,
University of Pittsburgh Press, 1963,
p.13; cf. Rescher, Nicholas, The Development of Arabic Logic, University
of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburg, 1964, p. 15.
[2] Ibn Taymiyyah mentions that Hasan ibn MËsÉ al-NawbakhtÊ (d.300
A.H./912) - the contemporary of ThÉbit ibn
Qurrah (d.288 A.H/900) - in
his KitÉb al-A<rÉ’ wa al-DiyÉnÉt pointed
out the fallacy of Aristotelian logic. Interestingly al-NazzÉm (d.231 A.H/845) and al-Jubba’Ê (d.303 A.H/915) of the rationalists Mu‘tazilite were against the philosophy of Aristotle. The following
criticism was from AbË Zakariyya al-RÉzÊ
(d.313 A.H./925) the eminent opponent of
Aristotle’s philosophy, but at the
same time he supported Pythagoras.
Moreover, Ibn Hazm al-AndalËsÊ (d.456 A.H./1063) also opposed Aristotle’s philosophy. Hibat Allah
Ibn ‘AlÊ AbË al-BarakÉt al-BaghdÉdÊ (d.548 A.H/1155) the author of KitÉb al-Mu‘tabar fÊ
al-Hikmah criticised Aristotle. For Ibn Taymiyyah’s notion of al-NawbakhtÊ, see al-Radd,
ed.R.’Ajam, vol.II. pp.84-86. For the
Muslim refutation of Aristotle’s
philosophy, see Sirajul Haque, “Ibn Taymiyyah, Life and
Works”, in M.M.Sharif, A History of
Muslim Philosophy, Otto Harrassowitz Wiesbaden, 1966, pp. 804-805.
[3] A lucid example on this case was
the attack and censure of Muslim scholars, like AbË al-WafÉ‘ Ibn ‘AqÊl (d.513 A.H./1119), al-TurtËsÊ (d.520 A.H./1126), Ibn al-ÎalÉh (d.643 A.H./1245), al-NawÉwÊ (d.631 A.H./1233), towards
al-Ghazzali, one of the most celebrated Muslim logicians. See al-NashshÉr, ‘AlÊ SÉmÊ, ManÉhij al-Bahth ‘inda Mufakkir al-Islam, DÉr al-Ma’Érif, Cairo , p. 143.
[4] The reason for choosing these two theories can be traced through the
historical fact that in the fourth/tenth century Arabic logicians had held that
definition is used for obtaining new concepts
(taÎawwurÉt) proceeding from some
pre-existent axiomatic knowledge. Moreover, they also believe that syllogism is
the only argument capable of yielding apodictic knowledge and the only tool
which can result in certitude. See Ibn SÊnÉ, al-ShifÉ’: al-ManÏ}iq, Madkhal, ed.al-Abb QanawÉtÊ et al, MaÏba’ah al-AmÊriyyah, Cairo ,
1952, p. 17.
[5] To prove this,
Ibn Taymiyyah points out that in
Islam there are sciences like Nahw, (Grammar), Lughah (language), ‘ArËd (prosody) Fiqh (jurisprudence)
UÎËl al-Fiqh (principle of
jurisprudence), and others, but to
him none of the scholars of these sciences
dealt with logic. See Naqd
al-ManÏiq, p. 169.
[6] The organisation of al-ManÏiq in
Arabic terms and its original
Aristotelian texts are: al-IsÉghujÊ (Isagoge,
introduction), al-maqËlÉt (Categoriae, Categories), al-’ibÉrah (De Interpretatione, Hermeneutic), al-qiyÉs (Analytica Priora, Analytics), al-burhÉn (Analytica Posteriora, Apodictics), al-jadal (Topica, Topics), al-mughÉliÏah or al-safsaÏah (Sophistici
Elenchi, Sophistics (al-khiÏÉbah) Rhetorica, Rhetoric, al-shi’r (Poetica,
Poetics). See Rescher, Nicholas, Studies
In The History of Arabic Logic, pp.13-14.
Ibn Taymiyyah also mentions the eight divisions of logic and Arabic translations of the terms. See al-Radd, ed. R ‘Ajam, vol. I, p. 52-53.
[7] MajmË‘at al-FatÉwÉ, vol.IX, pp. 269-270.
[8] Ibid, pp. 25-26.
[9] MuwÉfaqat, pp. 14-15.
[10] al-NashshÉr, ‘AlÊ SÉmÊ, ManÉhij al-Bahth, p. 143.
[11] al-Radd, ed.’Abd al-Îamad, p. 42.
[12] al-Ghazzali, al-MustaÎfÉ min UÎËl al-Fiqh, MaÏba’ah
al-AmÊriyah, 2 vols., Cairo ,
1904.
[13] al-Radd, ed.R.’Ajam, vol.I. p. 196; cf. al-Ghazzali, al-MustaÎfÉ, vol. I p. 10.
[14] al- NashshÉr, ManÉhij al-Bahth, p. 143.
[15] MajmË‘at al-FatÉwÉ, vol.IX, pp. 5-6; Naqd al-ManÏiq, p. 1.
[16] al-Radd, ed.’Abd al-Îamad, p. 4.
[17]al-Radd, ed. ‘ Abd al-Îamad, p. 4 Aristotle’s definition of ‘definition’ is a phrase signifying the
essence of a thing or the statement of a thing’s nature. See Farhang Zabeeh, Avicenna’s Treatise on Logic, Part One, Martinus Nijhoff, The
Hague , 1971, p. 18.
[18] Farhang Zabeeh, Avicenna’s Treatise on Logic, Part One, p. 29.