Rabu, 24 April 2013

al-Ghazali on the Doctrine of Creation


We have mentioned above that just as Ghazali’s concept of God has conceptual centrality, his concept of the Omnipotent God has profound bearing upon his concept of creation and the causal theory that he subscribes. In this concept, God is depicted as the Transcendental Creator of the world. He exists by Himself and is eternal and everlasting. The centrality of the concept of God in Ghazali’s thought is discernible from his affirmation and vindication of the concept of divine attributes, where divine power and will are the principal elements in his concept of creation. Therefore, the world, which means to him “everything other than God”,[1] is brought into existence, out of nothingness, by Him through the process of creation.

The starting point of Ghazali’s doctrine of creation is that the universe has a beginning in time. In his IqtiÎÉd he couched his argument in such a strong syllogistic form that serves also as an argument for God’s existence:
“Every being which begins has a cause for its beginning; now the world is being which begins; therefore, it possesses a cause for its beginning” (kullu ÍÉdithin faliÍudËthihÊ sabab, wa al-‘Élam ÍÉdithun fayalzam minhu anna lahu sababan).[2]

In his RisÉlah al-Ghazali reiterates the same argument that: “the world began in time; and they know by rational necessity that nothing which originates in time originates by itself, and that, therefore, it needs a creator”.[3] He even calls it the axiom of mind which is in itself obvious that anything that begins must have begun in a certain definite time. Its being definite in time and distinct from what preceded it and what succeeded it in existence, will naturally require determinant to select the time for its appearance.

In his TahÉfut the argument can be deduced into three premises and one conclusion as follows: 1) There are temporal events in the world; 2) The temporal events have causes; 3) The series of temporal events cannot regress infinitely.[4] Therefore, the series must stop at the eternal. The first premise is obvious since we experience in the world of the sense that there are around us things coming to be and passing away. The second premise is somewhat strange, for here al-Ghazali seems to be admitting the existence of secondary causation which he thoroughly repudiates. But if we look the addressee of the argument, i.e. the philosophers, who believed in the existence of real cause in the world, we understand it as a concession to his opponents. In other words al-Ghazali argues for the sake of his opponents that there are temporal phenomena in the world and these phenomena are preceded by other temporal phenomena, and so on. The premise does not uphold that the causation in the world is independent of God. The third premise is the crux of the argument that directly goes against the argument of the eternity of the world.  The gist behind this premise can be discerned from his query on the standpoint of his opponent on the infinite regress of temporal phenomena.

So, Ghazali’s premise that the world began in time is clear, for time itself had a beginning and was created.[5] Al-Ghazali does not denounce the Aristotelian definition of time as the measure of motion, nor does he question the legitimacy of the inference of the eternity of motion from the eternity of time.[6] Nonetheless, he upholds the argument that if temporal phenomena, or change in time have an origin, then time, as the measure of such change, must have an origin as well.

The above doctrine of creation is then applied into the principle of causality for the existence of all created things. Ghazali's position is clear that no created thing comes about through another (created being), all temporal events came about through the power of God, exalted be He.[7] al-Ghazali alters the term cause in the falÉsifah sense with the term ‘agent’. The argument to prove the divine power as an agent is couched as follows:
Every well-designed act proceeds from a powerful agent; the world is a well-designed, ordered act; therefore the world proceeds from a powerful agent.[8]

The argument is logically valid, yet he does not explain the first premise concerning the world design. It seems that he does not feel necessary to explain further, because of his conviction that such a premise “is apprehensible by sense (Íiss) and by observation (mushÉhadah) and hence is impossible to deny”,[9] and he regards this kind of knowledge as self-evident (ÌarËrat al-‘aql). al-Ghazali prefers to regard God as a powerful agent, rather than a First Cause in the falÉsifah sense, because by conceding God as a cause they mean that His act proceeds by virtue of His essence. If this were the case, the act would be co-eternal with the essence, or if God acts through His essence, His very essence necessitates His act, which is impossible. He is thus compelled to act. He has no choice and so has neither will nor power. The truth, according to Ghazali, is that an act proceeds from a meaning additional to the essence, which is called the attribute of power.[10]
Ghazali’s argument is back to the Ash’arite views. God, for the Ash’arite, is an agent, not a cause. Agent is a term applicable for a living, willing and knowing being. An agent does not act or create because of necessity. He does not create by “nature” (bi al-Ïab‘).[11] This concept of agent which is the basis of Ash’arite’s proof for the existence of God,[12] is to be found in al-BÉqillÉnÊ's TamhÊd that the world cannot be eternal; it must have a creator; and this creator must be a living, willing, knowing agent. In a lengthy argument, he ardently insists that God does not act through any necessity in His nature.[13] Ghazali, in QawÉ‘d al-‘AqÉid, reproduces similar proof for creation ex nihilo,  and for God’s existence.[14]

In his TahÉfut, al-Ghazali provides more space to discuss this issue and maintain that the term agent (al-fÉ‘il) entails the idea of will and the knowledge of the thing willed. A simple example, given by Ghazali, is that if someone throws another into the fire and the latter dies, it is said that the former is the agent of killing and not the fire, because the former has will and the knowledge. Hence the term agent is applicable only to animate beings. In this regard, God cannot be depicted as similar to inanimate, for He always acts by will.

By positing God as the agent of creation al-Ghazali does not have any problem in proving the existence of the world at a specific time. It is because His power and will play a pervasive role in the process of creation. Ghazali's argues  that divine power is attached to divine will. For him every object of power is at the same time an object of will (nurÉd); therefore everything that exists in time is an object of will (kullu hÉdith murÉd). It seems that al-Ghazali distinguishes God’s power from God’s will, but both work together when it stands in nexus with thing existing in time (ÍawÉdith). This position was then disapproved of by Ayn al-QuÌÉÍ al-HamdÉnÊ who posits that there is no difference between qudrah and irÉdah.[15] In fact, al-Ghazali was not entirely wrong for if we refer to the Qur’an: “Verily when He wills a thing, His command is Be and it is” (ÎËrah YÉsÊn:82), we discern that the will precedes the power; and for al-Ghazali this verse conveys the idea of the ultimate power. In Ghazali’s concept, the existence of the world at a specific time can be proven on the basis of such power-will attachment, meaning that Divine power is not undistinguishable from divine will, but attached to it; and that all temporal events were brought about by divine power, while the time of its occurrence is chosen and decreed by the divine will.

Moreover, al-Ghazali asserts that divine attributes (khuÎËÎ al-ÎifÉt) has specific effect, which are manifest in the world in the form of specific measure (miqdÉr makhÎËÎ) and specific position. The world as we experience it is, in fact, ‘specified’, and therefore, there must be something which specifies its existence and its non-existence and this specifier is that which is called will. The principle offered by al-Ghazali on this point is that will stand in nexus with all temporal events and that every temporal event (ÍÉdithÉt) is created by God’s power (kullu ÍÉdith fa mukhtara‘ bi qudratihi) and everything created by God power stands in need of the divine will (kullu mukhtara‘ bi al-Qudrah muÍtÉj ilÉ irÉdatin).

The world comes to be at the time when eternal will stands in nexus with its coming to be at that time without the occurrence of a new will or changing in the eternal will. This principle is based on the concept of seven essential attributes, in which God does not will essentially, but will by virtue of a will. So the divine will is itself determinant, as he characterized it in a sentence “what He wills is and what He does not will is not”.[16]

However, just as God’s will is attached with power, it is also related to knowledge. In his QawÉ‘id al-‘AqÉ’id al-Ghazali depicts God as the one who creates, governs and knows everything. Everything was created with measure. The universe is contrived by knowledge and wisdom of One Author in a single scheme. So everything works together according to the measure and has its place and importance that are assigned to it by God. He watches over all and He is nearer to man than his jugular vein. He rewards each according to his part. Though God’s power is infinite and absolute, He will never violate anything in the scheme according to which the universe moves.[17] This portrayal does not deviate too far from the concept of causality in the Qur’an that we have elaborated in Chapter One, yet we shall prove in more detail in Chapter Four, especially in his concept of particularization (takhÎÊs).

So, it is clear from the above argument that Ghazali’s argument of creation corroborates the concept of God who has creative power and who is the only creator of the world. Just as creation implies the act of creating, the concept of living God cannot be depicted as the Agent, but as the powerful Agent. Certainly the whole argument on creation diametrically opposes the philosophers’ argument of emanation.[18] Their concept of emanation, adopted from Plotinian theory, considers the world to be a necessary outflow from the being of God, like light from the sun, and hence no will, power and knowledge are entailed. Therefore, it is not a coincidence that their theory of emanation is parallel to their denial of divine attribute which, according to Ghazali, arises from their over-emphasis on the abstract unity and absolute perfection of God. Therefore, Ghazali’s argument noticeably vindicates the primacy of the divine will in the whole process of world origination, whereas the falÉsifah defended the unity of God’s essence in so absolute ways that they disallow any notion that would imply the act of creation. The falÉsifah justify the Aristotelian “necessitarianism” and Plotinian doctrine of emanation and hence maintain the doctrine of the eternity of the world. In contrast, al-Ghazali maintains the concept of the creative power of God that has some bearing upon the concept of the creation of the world.  His renowned theory of causality is basically the necessary corollary of this concept, which came into conflict with the falÉsifah’s doctrine of necessity.




[1] Ibid., 29.
[2] Ibid.
[3] The book is part of “KitÉb QawÉ’id al-‘AqÉ’id,’ of IÍyÉ’, vol.I, translated with notes by Nabih Amin Faris, “al-Ghazali, The Foundation of the Article of Faith”, Sh.Muhammad Ashraf, Lahore, 1974, 59-60.
[4] Al-Ghazali, TahÉfut,  ed.& trans. by Marmura, , 27, translation is taken from Marmura with some modification.
[5] Ibid., 36.
[6] Marmura have the same conclusion, see Michael E. Marmura, ‘The Logical Role of The Argument from Time in the TahÉfut’s Second Proof for the World’s Pre-eternity’, Muslim World, 49 (1959), 306.
[7] Al-Ghazali, al-IqtiÎÉd, ed. M.AbË al-‘AlÉ,  90.
[8] Ibid., 75.
[9] Ibid.
[10]  Ibid., 76.
[11] This point of view is not only directed against the falÉsifah, but also against the Mu’tazilah. See Ibn ×azm, KitÉb al-FiÎal, 5 vols., vol. III,  55, 58.
[12]. Al-Ash’arÊ, KitÉb al-Luma’, edited and translated by Richard Mcarty (Beyruth): Imprimerie Catholique, 1953, Arabic text, 6-7; English translation 6-8. 
[13] Al-BÉqillÉnÊ, KitÉb TamhÊd al-AwÉ’il wa TalkhÊÎ al-DalÉil, edited ‘ImÉd al-DÊn AÍmad ×aydar, (Beirut: Mu’assasat al-Kutub al-ThaqÉfiyyah, 1987/1407):  44,47-48, and 52-56.
[14] Al-Ghazali, IÍyÉ’, ed. A.A.  SirwÉn , vol. I,  181-182.
[15] For ‘Ayn al-QuÌÉÍ’s statement see Omar Jah, Zubdah al-×aqÉ’iq, An annotated English translation from Arabic, (Kuala Lumpur: ISTAC, 2000), 13; Cf. Al-Ghazali,  QawÉ‘id al-‘AqÉid, English trans., 45.
[16] Al-Ghazali, al-IqtiÎÉd, ed. M.AbË al-‘AlÉ 108.
[17] Al-Ghazali, “QawÉ‘id al-‘AqÉ’id fÊ al-TawhÊd”, in al-QuÎËr al-‘AwÉlÊ min RasÉ’il al-Ghazali, vol. IV, ed. (Cairo: MuÎÏafÉ AbË al-‘AlÉ, Maktabah al-JundÊ, 1972): 149-150.
[18] For good discussion on this discrepancy see M.Saeed Sheikh, “al-Ghazali Metaphysics” in M.M.Sharif, History of Muslim Philosophy, 601-608.  

Jalaluddin Rumi, Penyair Sufi Terbesar dari Konya-Persia

          Dua orang bertengkar sengit di suatu jalan di Konya. Mereka saling memaki, “O, laknat, jika kau mengucapkan sepatah makian terh...